Who is a realist philosopher




















This object is abstract because it has no spatial or temporal location, and is causally inert. The main arguments against platonic realism turn on the idea that the platonist position precludes a satisfactory epistemology of arithmetic. For the classic exposition of the doubt that platonism can square its claims to accommodate knowledge of arithmetical truth with its conception of the subject matter of arithmetic as causally inert, see Benacerraf Benacerraf argued that platonism faces difficulties in squaring its conception of the subject-matter of arithmetic with a general causal constraint on knowledge roughly, that a subject can be said to know that P only if she stands in some causal relation to the subject matter of P.

In response, platonists have attacked the idea that a plausible causal constraint on ascriptions of knowledge can be formulated Wright Ch. Rather, Field suggests that not only has the platonic realist no recourse to any explanation of reliability that is causal in character, but that she has no recourse to any explanation that is non-causal in character either. For Field, the utility of mathematical theories resides not in their truth but in their conservativeness , where a mathematical theory S is conservative if and only if for any nominalistically respectable statement A i.

How might one argue for such a radical-sounding thesis? The conceptual claim is that moral facts are objective and categorically prescriptive facts, or, equivalently, that our concept of a moral property is a concept of an objective and categorically prescriptive quality what Mackie means by this is explained below. The ontological claim is simply that there are no objective and categorically prescriptive facts, that objective and categorically prescriptive properties are nowhere instantiated.

The conclusion is that there is nothing in the world answering to our moral concepts, no facts or properties which render the judgements formed via those moral concepts true. Our moral atomic moral judgements are systematically false. We can thus construe the argument for the error-theory as follows:.

The conclusion of this argument clearly follows from its premises, so the question facing those who wish to defend at least the existence dimension of realism in the case of morals is whether the premises are true. Note that strictly speaking what the argument purports to establish is that there are no moral facts as-we-conceive-of-them.

What does this mean? To say that moral requirements are prescriptive is to say that they tell us how we ought to act, to say that they give us reasons for acting. Thus, to say that something is morally good is to say that we ought to pursue it, that we have reason to pursue it. To say that something is morally bad is to say that we ought not to pursue it, that we have reason not to pursue it. The reasons for action that moral requirements furnish are not contingent upon the possession of any desires or wants on the part of the agent to whom they are addressed: I cannot release myself from the requirement imposed by the claim that torturing the innocent is wrong by citing some desire or inclination that I have.

Reasons for action which are contingent in this way on desires and inclinations are furnished by what Kant called hypothetical imperatives. So our concept of a moral requirement is a concept of a categorically prescriptive requirement. But Mackie claims further that our concept of a moral requirement is a concept of an objective and categorically prescriptive requirement.

What does it mean to say that a requirement is objective? Mackie says a lot of different-sounding things about this, and the following as outlined in Miller a is by no means a comprehensive list references are to Ch. To call a requirement objective is to say that it can be an object of knowledge 24, 31, 33 , that it can be true or false 26, 33 , that it can be perceived 31, 33 , that it can be recognised 42 , that it is prior to and independent of our preferences and choices 30, 43 , that it is a source of authority external to our preferences and choices 32, 34, 43 , that it is part of the fabric of the world 12 , that it backs up and validates some of our preferences and choices 22 , that it is capable of being simply true 30 or valid as a matter of general logic 30 , that it is not constituted by our choosing or deciding to think in a certain way 30 , that it is extra-mental 23 , that it is something of which we can be aware 38 , that it is something that can be introspected 39 , that it is something that can figure as a premise in an explanatory hypothesis or inference 39 , and so on.

Mackie plainly does not take these to be individually necessary: facts about subatomic particles, for example, may qualify as objective in virtue of figuring in explanatory hypotheses even though they cannot be objects of perceptual acquaintance.

But his intention is plain enough: these are the sorts of conditions whose satisfaction by a fact renders it objective as opposed to subjective. This issue cannot be discussed in detail here, except to note that while it seems plausible to claim that if our concept of a moral fact is a concept of a reason for action then that concept must be a concept of a categorical reason for action, it is not so clear why we have to say that our concept of a moral fact is a concept of a reason for action at all.

For exposition and critical discussion, see Miller a , Ch. For a useful discussion, see Brink The argument from queerness has both metaphysical and epistemological components.

Thus, the world contains no moral states of affairs, situations which consist in the instantiation of a moral quality. In short, our ordinary conceptions of how we might come into cognitive contact with states of affairs, and thereby acquire knowledge of them, cannot cope with the idea that the states of affairs are objective values.

So we are forced to expand that ordinary conception to include forms of moral perception and intuition. But these are completely unexplanatory: they are really just placeholders for our capacity to form correct moral judgements the reader should here hear an echo of the complaints Benacerraf and Field raise against arithmetical platonism.

Evaluating the argument from queerness is well outwith the scope of the present entry. Examples of the latter version, and attempts to provide the owed response to the argument from queerness, can be found in Smith , Ch. For an example of such a strategy, see Cuneo For a general discussion, see Lillehammer Mackie claims that the error-theory of moral judgement is a second-order theory, which does not necessarily have implications for the first order practice of making moral judgements Suppose we can extract from this story some subsidiary norm distinct from truth, which governs the practice of forming moral judgements.

See Kalderon and Joyce for examples. For a book-length treatment of moral error-theory, see Olson The error-theories proposed by Mackie and Field are non-eliminativist error-theories, and should be contrasted with the kind of eliminativist error-theory proposed by e. Paul Churchland concerning folk-psychological propositional attitudes see Churchland Churchland argues that our everyday talk of propositional attitudes such as beliefs, desires and intentions should eventually be abandoned given developments in neuroscience.

Mackie and Field make no analogous claims concerning morality and arithmetic: no claim, that is, to the effect that they will one day be in principle replaceable by philosophically hygienic counterparts. For some discussion of the contrast between eliminativist and non-eliminativist error theories, see Miller Although some commentators e. There are a number of reasons for this, with the reasons varying depending on the type of reduction proposed.

Suppose, first of all, that one wished to deny the existence claim which is a component of platonic realism about arithmetic. One way to do this would be to propose an analytic reduction of talk seemingly involving abstract entities to talk concerning only concrete entities. This can be illustrated by considering a language the truth of whose sentences seemingly entails the existence of a type of abstract object, directions.

A number of contextual definitions are now introduced:. After all, A , B , and C allow us to paraphrase any sentence whose truth appears to entail the existence of abstract objects into a sentence whose truth involves only the existence of concrete inscriptions.

There is a powerful argument, first developed by William Alston , and convincingly resuscitated by Crispin Wright , Ch. The analytic reductionist who wishes to wield the contextual definitions against the existence claim at the heart of platonic realism takes them to show that the apparent reference to abstract objects on the left-hand sides of the definitions is merely apparent: in fact, the truth of the relevant sentences entails only the existence of a range of concrete inscriptions.

But the platonic realist can retort: what the contextual definitions show is that the apparent lack of reference to abstract objects on the right-hand sides is merely apparent. In fact, the platonic realist can say, the truth of the sentences figuring on the right-hand sides implicitly involves reference to abstract objects. If there is no way to break this deadlock the existence of the analytic reductive paraphrases will leave the existence claim at the heart of the relevant form of realism untouched.

So the issue of this style of reductionism appears to be orthogonal to debates between realists and non-realists. Can the same be said about non-analytic styles of reductionism? Again, there is no straightforward connection between the issue of reductionism and the issue of realism. The problem is that, to borrow some terminology and examples from Railton , some reductions will be vindicative whilst others will be eliminativist. For example, the reduction of water to H 2 0 is vindicative: it vindicates our belief that there is such a thing as water, rather than overturning it.

On the other hand:. Thus, a non-analytic reduction may or may not have implications for the existence dimension of a realistic view of a particular subject matter. Again, there is no straightforward relationship between the issue of reductionism and the issue of realism. We saw above that for the subject-matter in question the error-theorist agrees with the realist that the truth of the atomic, declarative sentences of that area requires the existence of the relevant type of objects, or the instantiation of the relevant sorts of properties.

We also saw that an error-theory about a particular area could be motivated by epistemological worries Field or by a combination of epistemological and metaphysical worries Mackie. Another way in which the existence dimension of realism can be resisted is via expressivism. Whereas the realist and the error-theorist agree that the sentences of the relevant area are truth-apt , apt to be assessed in terms of truth and falsity, the realist and the expressivist alternatively non-cognitivist, projectivist disagree about the truth-aptness of those sentences.

But there are other grammatical moods that are conventionally associated with different types of speech-act. Note that we would not ordinarily think of orders or questions as even apt for assessment in terms of truth and falsity: they are not truth-apt.

The expressivist about a particular area will claim that the realist is misled by the syntax of the sentences of that area into thinking that they are truth-apt: she will say that this is a case where the conventional association of the declarative mood with assertoric force breaks down.

There are some very important issues concerning the relationship between minimalism about truth-aptitude and expressivism that we cannot go into here.

See Divers and Miller and Miller b for some pointers. There are also some important differences between e. For a useful account, see Schroeder So, if moral sentences are not conventionally used for the making of assertions, what are they conventionally used for?

According to one classical form of expressivism, emotivism , they are conventionally used for the expression of emotion, feeling, or sentiment. Thus, A. Ayer writes:. Emotivism faces many problems, discussion of which is not possible here for a survey, see Miller a Ch.

But what about contexts in which it is not being applied to an action type? But now there is a problem in accounting for the following valid inference:. So the above argument is apparently no more valid than:.

According to theories like these, moral modus ponens arguments such as the argument above from 1 and 2 to 3 are just like non-moral cases of modus ponens such as. Throughout, the semantic function of the sentences concerned is given in terms of the states of affairs asserted to obtain in simple assertoric contexts.

Philosophers wishing to develop an expressivistic alternative to moral realism have expended a great deal of energy and ingenuity in devising responses to this challenge. For an overview, see Schroeder and Miller a , Chs 4 and 5. For very useful surveys of recent work on expressivism, see Schroeder and Sinclair Examples of challenges to the existence dimension of realism have been described in previous sections.

In this section some forms of non-realism that are neither error-theoretic nor expressivist will be briefly introduced. The forms of non-realism view the sentences of the relevant area as against the expressivist truth-apt, and against the error-theorist at least sometimes true. The existence dimension of realism is thus left intact. Classically, opposition to the independence dimension of realism about the everyday world of macroscopic objects took the form of idealism , the view that the objects of the everyday world of macroscopic objects are in some sense mental.

As Berkeley famously claimed, tables, chairs, cats, the moons of Jupiter and so on, are nothing but ideas in the minds of spirits:. One such philosopher, Michael Dummett, has suggested that in some cases it may be appropriate to reject the independence dimension of realism via the rejection of semantic realism about the area in question see Dummett and It is easiest to characterise semantic realism for a mathematical domain.

It is a feature of arithmetic that there are some arithmetical sentences for which the following holds true: we know of no method that will guarantee us a proof of the sentence, and we know of no method that will guarantee us a disproof or a counterexample either.

It is possible that we may come across a proof, or a counterexample, but the key point is that we do not know a method, or methods, the application of which is guaranteed to yield one or the other. To say that the notion of truth involved is potentially recognition-transcendent is to say that G may be true or false even though there is no guarantee that we will be able, in principle, to recognise that that is so.

To say that the notion of truth involved is bivalent is to accept the unrestricted applicability of the law of bivalence, that every meaningful sentence is determinately either true or false. Thus the semantic realist is prepared to assert that G is determinately either true or false, regardless of the fact that we have no guaranteed method of ascertaining which.

Note that the precise relationship between the characterisation in terms of bivalence and that in terms of potentially recognition-transcendent truth is a delicate matter that will not concern us here.

Thus, people cannot see or otherwise come into sensory contact with universals, and it is meaningless to apply the categories of space and time to them, but they can nevertheless be conceived of and exist. One type of universal defined by Plato is the Form , which is not a mental entity at all, but rather an idea or archetype or original model of which particular objects, properties and relations are copies.

The "forms" small "f" or appearances that we see, according to Plato , are not real, but literally mimic the real "Forms" capital "F". Forms are capable of being instantiated by one or many different particulars , which are essentially material copies of the Forms - the particulars are said to "participate" in the Forms, and the Forms are said to "inhere" in the particulars.

According to Plato , Platonic Forms possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality. They are perfect because they are unchanging. The world of Forms is separate from our own world the world of substances and is the true basis of reality. Removed from matter, Forms are the most pure of all things.

True knowledge or intelligence is the ability to grasp the world of Forms with one's mind. Plato 's main evidence for the existence of Forms is intuitive only, arguing from human perception a generalization which applies equally to objects which are clearly different e. Plato himself was well aware of the limitations of his theory, and in particular concocted the "Third Man Argument" against his own theory: if a Form and a particular are alike , then there must be another third thing by possession of which they are alike, leading to an infinite regression.

In a later rather unsatisfactory version of the theory, he tried to circumvent this objection by positing that particulars do not actually exist as such: they "mime" the Forms, merely appearing to be particulars.

Aristotle points out that proof of Forms and universals rests on prior knowledge : if we did not know what universals were in the first place, we would have no idea of what we were trying to prove , and so could not be trying to prove it.

He also asserted that universals and particulars imply each other : one is logically prior or posterior to the other and, if they are to be regarded as distinct , then they cannot be "universal" and "particulars". Other critics have argued that Forms, not being spatial , cannot have a shape, so it cannot be that a particular of, say, an apple is the same shape as the Form of an apple. They have also questioned how one can have the concept of a Form existing in some special realm of the universe, apart from space and time, since such a concept cannot come from sense-perception.

Moderate Realism is the view that there is no separate realm where universals or universal concepts exist, but that they are located in space and time wherever they happen to be manifest.

Apply for Admission. View Brochure. Enquire Now. Virtual Tour. Student Credit Card Scheme. Reading of the Preamble. Realism and Aims of Education: Realism explains the aims of education in different perspectives. Preparation for a Happy and Successful Life: The first and most important aim of realistic education is to prepare learners for a happy and successful life.

The American educationist, Franklin Bobit has given following activities for achieving happiness in life: Activities related to language Activities concerned with hygiene Citizenship activities Social activities Leisure activities Religious activities Vocational activities Activities of mental health Activities related to vocational behaviour Activities related to race-preservation Preparation for Practical Life: Realism recommends preparing students for real and practical life of material world which can be gained through senses.

Training of Senses: Realism believes that fullest development of personality can be possible through proper training of senses. The learners will not have a proper knowledge about the material world unless their senses are trained and improved properly. Developing Physical and Mental Powers: The physical and mental powers are required for developing intelligence, discrimination and judgements by which learners will be able to overcome the challenges of life. Developing Vocational Efficiency: This type of realistic aim makes education craft-centric.

Realism is in favour of developing vocational efficiencies among learners so that they can prepare themselves for fulfilling livelihood demands.

Realism and Method of Teaching: Realism aims to prepare learners for real and practical life. It calls for teaching-learning methodologies on the basis of subjects and interests of the learners. Classical Greece. World War II. B July 16, , pm Reply. You have a really nice blog here. It explains the philosophies in ways that my non philosophical mind could understand.

Please keep it up! Anonymous March 6, , pm Reply. Interesting read. God Bless. Max March 11, , am Reply. Realism I. Quiz 1. Which quote is an expression of philosophical realism? Realism is often contrasted with…. This film deals with themes of realism and anti-realism:. The realism-idealism debate dates back at least to….



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000